Back to the Syllabus


6. Optimal Foraging Theory

Barry Sinervo©1997


Index

Optimal Foraging and Adaptational Hypotheses

Optimal Food Choice

Optimal Clam Size in the Foraging Crow

Mussel Size Selection by Oyster Catchers

The Theorems of Optimal Foraging

The Marginal Value-Theorem: Patch Residence Time

The Ideal Free Distribution: Patch Quality and Competitors

Central Place Foraging

Perceptual Constraints on Optimal Foraging?

The Search Image

Rats in radial arms

Risk Aversion and Reward: Foraging Ecology of Bumble Bees

Foraging in Juncos and Risk Aversion Under Energy Limitation

Foraging & Biotic Interactions

Group Foraging

Predation Risk



Optimal Foraging and Adaptational Hypotheses

Attacks on the adaptational paradigm in the late 70's (Gould and Lewontin 1978) precipitated a flurry of activity in behavioral ecology, especially in the field of Optimal Foraging Theory. Gould and Lewontin addressed many weaknesses in the adaptationists paradigm, but the most biting challenge related to the notion that all phenotypic traits in an organism must be the result of natural selection. Gould and Lewontin's arguments related to what they referred to as the "Adaptationist's Programme". Programme is a reference to a way of doing science or a metaphor for a computer program that would describe how an Adaptationist (what some have referred to as foaming adaptationists) carry out research. While the basic "adaptationist's programme" as described by Gould and Lewontin (1978) is a caricature of the actual adaptationist's method, their attacks did force the entire field to look closely at the inferences people were making regarding the utility of traits under study. Researchers became more sensitized to alternative non-adaptational hypotheses. Despite these attacks, the Adaptationist's Programme is alive and well. It is a step by step process in which the scientist must:

  1. identify the trait that is likely to be under selection
  2. construct a functional argument for how that trait might lead to adaptive value
  3. in the case of optimal foraging theory, assume that energy maximization is related to fitness
  4. determine whether the mean value of the trait in the population is "optimal" in terms of organismal design and function (e.g., energy maximization).
  5. if the trait is not found to be under optimizing selection, then go back to step 2 and construct a new functional argument or come up with another trait or perhaps other factors not considered that might lead to the discrepancy between the observed value of the trait and the "optimality arguments".

The last step is how the metaphor relates to a computer program. By looping back to the beginning if you do not get a correct "optimal" answer, the adaptationist is sure to come up with an adaptational explanation if they try hard enough. The other factors not considered in the first loop of the program that could be taken up in subsequent loops could be:

  1. other traits that cause a tradeoff,
  2. mechanisms that influence the function of the trait (e.g., hardness of prey)
  3. constraints arising from time limitations, or
  4. biotic agents (e.g., predators or competitors) that might influence the decision making.

All of these alternatives are still well within the realm of adaptational hypotheses. Suffice it to say that Gould and Lewontin offered alternative, non-adaptational hypotheses that might explain organismal traits. Many of their arguments relate to constraints on design that arise from development and organismal architecture. We will consider Gould and Lewontin's arguments regarding constraint in some detail in subsequent Chapters and I will briefly touch upon these ideas when I discuss memory limitations and constraints on cognition during foraging. For the moment let us consider the specific examples of optimal foraging theory and adaptationism and the data that researchers have collected in recent years.

The assumption in the third step is critical to optimal foraging theory as we assume that energy maximization or optimization is in some way related to fitness maximization (e.g., stabilizing selection on the trait of interest). Much of optimal foraging theory rests on this assumption. In some of the examples described below it is clear that the researchers have to be careful to consider alternative energy maximization rules.

I will begin a few examples of organisms that appear to be using optimal decision making. The we will explore some theoretical concepts that are useful in understanding the behavioral decisions that animals make. These theoretical ideas will be followed with examples of animals foraging in the wild. In the spirit of Gould and Lewontin, I will end with a discussion of the perceptual constraints on foraging that might limit the choices that animals make in the wild.

Index


Food Choice: Prey Size

One of the simplest issues in foraging decisions is picking the food that leads to the highest rate of energy acquisition. How large a prey item should an organism attempt to eat.

Rule number one:

Never eat anything bigger than your head.

Rule number two:

Eat items that lead to the highest gain in Energy/Time. (assuming that you are maximizing energy.)

Profitability = Energy Gain/Unit of Time.

Index


Optimal Clam Size in the Foraging Crow

Richardson and Verbeek studied Crows foraging on clams in the intertidal and noticed that they left quite a few clams behind after digging them up.

If they go to the trouble of digging them up in the first place why not eat them?

The answer lies in handling time -- how long it would take them to open the clam.

The choice lies in whether to open a particular clam or search for a larger clam.

A simple calculation of whether:

(Gain small)/handling time < (Gain large)/(search time + handling time)

would determine the optimal foraging rule.

Richardson and Verbeek computed a model similar to the simple one presented above and came up with a prediction for the percentage of clams eaten as a function of size that is remarkably similar to that observed for the real data for crows.

Index


Mussel Size Selection by Oyster Catchers

A similar problem is faced by Oyster catchers trying to open mussels. Optimality model that only considers Energy maximization predicts that Oyster Catchers should choose the largest clams that they encounter.

However, Oyster Catchers do not always choose the largest mussels, often leaving them untouched.

Why leave the biggest items?

The handling time for the largest mussels leads to a dramatic drop in profitability and Oyster Catchers should avoid them from the start.

The example of Oyster Catchers illustrates the approach of the Optimal Foraging Ecologist. It is not that they are searching for reasons for a lack of fit with an unsuitable model. Rather it is a stepwise process that leads to more and more elaborate models. Why start with a complicated explanation from the start -- choose the simplest explanation that will explain the pattern.

Index


The Theorems of Optimal Foraging

The Marginal Value Theorem: Patch Residence Time

The choice about when, where, and how long to settle or stop for a feeding bout is one of the basic decisions for an organism that is searching for resources among widely scattered patches. One of the simplest solutions in foraging ecology, the marginal value theorem, is easy to derive from a graphical analysis. The marginal value theorem yields the "giving up time" or when an organism should leave a patch that it is exploiting. As an animal begins feeding, it's energy gain gradually begins to slow down as food becomes scarcer in the patch. It takes longer and longer to find the next tasty morsel, thus the curve describing residence time in the patch and Energy Gain starts off with a steep slope but then gradually levels off.


When should the animal say enough is enough and move on to find the next patch? The crucial parameter that governs this decision is the travel time between patches. An animal gains no energy while traveling.

Fundamental value to maximize: An organism should try to maximize its net rate of energy gain (this includes time during which it cannot feed as it travels through a patch).


A rate of energy gain is expressed as calories gained per unit of time, which on the graph at the right is a straight line with slope given by the rise over run:

Energy Gain/Time.

The steepest line (gain/time) or line of greatest slope would be the one that maximizes the rate of energy gain. Thus, an animal that leaves too early has a shallow line (less energy per unit of time) relative to the maximum.



There is really no benefit in staying too long as those tasty treats are running out. The animal should move on to greener pastures. Consequently, an animal that leaves too late also has a shallow line relative to the line of maximum slope. The line that gives the maximum rate of energy gain is the line that hits the gain curve at a tangent (red line). The line of steepest slope which still intersects the gain curve, is the maximum net gain possible when you factor in the travel time between patches.


Finally, animals should also be sensitive to the length of time it takes to travel from patch to patch. When the travel time is short, they should leave far sooner than when the travel time between patches is very long.


 

Index


The Ideal Free Distribution: Patch Quality and Competitors

The previous discussion ignores any consideration of variation in patch quality, or competition from other animals. The concept of the ideal free distribution (Fretwell and Lucas, 1972) takes both of these factors into account in determining how animals should distribute themselves among patches. Ideal free refers to an animal that was free to move between patches under the ideal conditions of no constraints on movement. In such a case, the animals should distribute themselves in the place where the gains will be the highest. Lets consider the size of the patch to be a measure of quality. Animals would preferentially pour into the higher quality patch and tend to initially avoid the lower quality patches.


A problem arises for the individuals as more and more competitors pour into the high quality patch. If too many competitors pour into the high quality patch, then it would actually pay for some to move to the patch of next highest quality as the gains from such a patch would be higher than the first high quality patch that has now become too crowded. Animals continue to move among patches until their sampling efforts find the highest rate of gain. Individuals with low gain move to higher gain patches.


At equilibrium, all the patches are filled up, and the number of competitors present in each patch is proportional to the quality of the patch. Every competitor does equally well, and it would not pay to move among patches. The ideal free distribution is a very simple concept, but as it gets applied to animals in the wild, it appears to have some validity. The key is to pick the right time scale to observe animals making such ideal free decisions, and allowing them time to come to an equilibrium.


Additional references:

Sutherland, B. and Parker, G. A. 1985. in Behavioral Ecology, Edited by R. M. Sibly and R.H. Smith, pp 255-274.

Millinski, M. 1988. Games fish play. Trends in Ecology and Evolution 3:325-330.

Index


Central Place Foraging

The concept of central place foraging is a special case of the marginal value theorem. Animals that forage around a retreat site such as beavers with a lodge, ground squirrels around the colony, or ants around a nest are faced with movement away from a central location to the food resources. The question is, how many items should an individual collect before returning to the retreat, storehouse, or larder. Another question arises regarding how best to exploit the resource around the central retreat before perhaps moving on to the next site.

The central place foraging concept is intimately related to the marginal value theorem. In a field experiment with chipmunks, Kramer (1982) provided the chipmunks with patches of sunflower seeds at varying distances from their burrows. As the chipmunks stuffed their cheek pouches full, the rate of seed collection declined in a fashion that was similar to the theoretical gain curve. In addition, the chipmunks spent longer in each patch and took larger loads when they were collecting at more distant patches to their burrow. While these trends were present, their wasn't an exact match between the theoretical and predicated values suggesting that other factors might have played a role in the chipmunks"decision making".

Kacelnik studied central place foraging in parental starlings which have a nest site and forage in the vicinity of the nest site for their food making trips to collect multiple items. The question for a starling parent is how many items to collect in its bill before returning to feed its young? Kacelnik was able to train some birds to visit a feeder which dispensed mealworms at an ever increasing rate to simulate the decreasing gain curve of the marginal value theorem. In the case of parental starlings, is the parent tries to:

  1. maximize its total energy gained which is given by E/time, or
  2. maximize energy delivered to young which also entails the energy costs of the parent during travel as well as the energy costs for chicks or E/time - Ep - Ec.

By manipulating the gain curve, and altering the travel time or distance of the feeder box, Kacelnik found support for maximization rule #2. This indicates that the answer of what is optimal depends on what the animal might be interested in maximizing.

Index


Perceptual Constraints on Foraging?

Central place foraging assumes that animals have perfect information regarding their environment. They do not. They have to learn about their environment, and then as they learn, they must remember information about their environment. These cognitive processes place limits on the kinds of optimal choices that animals can make.

The Search Image

The first problem that an organism encounters during feeding is finding their prey item. Prey have have evolved elaborate adaptations to be cryptic. Classic examples of crypsis include moths on tree bark and the evolution of crypsis during the industrialization of the United Kingdom. Around areas with high rates of coal burning, the trees became sooty and a melanistic form of moth increased in frequency relative to the light-colored "typical" morph usually found on the grayish lichen in unpolluted areas. Is this a difference that makes a difference for the moth's survival? Is there additional natural selection on the cryptic morphs that further perfects their camouflage? The answer to these two questions is an overwhelming -- Yes! Predators can find a white moth on a black background more readily than they can a black moth (and vice versa). Then we might ask more intricate questions regarding the abilities of the predators.

Advocates for the idea of a search image maintain that predators use a few cues that identify particularly cryptic prey against the background that conceals the prey. Pietrewicz and Kamil (1979) tested aspects of the search image hypothesis using operant conditioning on blue jays. Under operant conditioning one tests whether subjects can learn some task. In this cryptic prey discrimination test, the jays pecked at a key in order to receive a reward for a correctly completed task.

Their experiment presented two kinds of slides during the Blue Jay's discrimination task:

  1. a moth present on a cryptic background
  2. no moth present.

This experiment had the following reward structure:

  1. If the blue jay pecked at the key when shown a cryptic moth they received a food reward
  2. If they pecked with not moth present, the did not receive food and the jay had to wait some length of time before it could relieve the next food item.

Experiment to test the search image:

One would predict that the Blue Jays would get better at the task (e.g., percentage correct) if they were presented with the same kind of moth.

Control Experiment:

However, if they were shown two different moths in a random order, they presumably could not lock in on a search image, and they should not necessarily get better at the discrimination task.

Results and Conclusions:

The Blue Jays got better with one type of prey suggesting that they formed a search image. However, they did not get better when randomly presented two prey species with different kinds of crypsis. These results suggest that they could not form a search image, or that they used the search image formed for one species, which reduced their efficiency during episodes with the other species.

The search image could form a short term constraint on finding prey. The amount of time it takes to learn search images my constrain how quickly an animal learns new ones. In addition, for organism that search for very different prey items the search image may not be very useful at all.


Additional Reading:

Pietrewicz, A. T., and A. C. Kamil. 1979. Search image formation in the blue jay Cyanocittata cristata. Science 204: 1332-1333.

Index


Rats in Radial Arms

Rats are thought to be central place foragers in that they move out from a central location (typically at night) and forage along pathways to patches with food. John P. Roche and William Timberlake looked at "The Influence of Paths and Landmarks on the Foraging of Norway Rats (Rattus norvegicus)". They were interested in how a natural map might influence the foraging decisions of the rats. Due to the advantages of following maps, the rat might be tuned to follow natural maps to get around in a complex world. The maze running ability of rats is a classic example in learning theory that demonstrates their capacity for dealing with spatial problems. Are rats constrained in their foraging by the way they think?

Roche and Timberlake got the rats to forage in radial arms that were just "roads" to provide structure. By manipulating the shape of the roads they could see whether path length began to override the natural tendency of rats to follow trackways.

Some Conclusions:

  1. Pathways had a larger influence on the orientation of foraging Norway rats than vertical visual cues (beacons); they were initially more helpful when they led to food, and more misleading when they did not lead to food, then beacons. These differences in the salience of orientation cues disappeared with time so that rats in different environmental conditions all foraged with statistically indistinguishable net rates of return.
  2. When pathways were elongated, and thus more energetically costly to follow, rats followed them less.

 

Excerpts from their discussion:

"The tendency to use paths to orient to food was influenced by the length and location of paths. Rats in the paths-to-food treatment approached food cups along paths a large proportion of the time. Rats in the crooked paths, on the other hand, used paths to orient to food an intermediate proportion of the time. Rats in the misaligned and short paths treatments infrequently used paths to approach food cups. Rats in the crooked paths treatment displayed significantly fewer approaches along paths, significantly more indirect arcs, and significantly more open travel, than rats in the paths-to-food treatment, indicating that whereas rats have a tendency to follow paths, they are sensitive to the length of those paths relative to the distance between food sites. Although approach of food cups from paths was low in the short and misaligned paths treatments, rats in the short paths treatment did approach cups from paths significantly more than rats in the misaligned paths treatment. Rats in the short paths treatment displayed significantly more direct arcs than rats in the other treatments with paths, perhaps because they were less "distracted" by paths.

Some animals use the paths for more than just the shortest route to food, but also as a means of orienting to food. However, such orientation responses can be overridden by making it more costly to follow paths to food suggesting that foraging efficiency will become more important and supplant the "benefits" of the pathway approach to food.

Index


Risk Aversion and Reward: Foraging Ecology of Bumble Bees

Leslie Real began a series of studies investigating the influence of unpredictability in the nectar reward that foraging bumble bees encounter. He asked a simple question that has led to some elegant questions of cognition and its role in foraging:

Are animals sensitive to unpredictability?

Given the choice between two flowers which have on average the same reward, but which differ in variance, which will bees tend to favor.

He set up the following experimental conditions:

  1. One color flower, blue, initially contained 2 microliters of nectar in every flower.
  2. The other flower, yellow, contained 6 microliters in every third flower and nothing in the other two flowers.
  3. The flowers were placed in a large array and randomized among the color types and rewards.
  4. Bees that were trained to grid were allowed to forage, and the reward was switched between color types half way through the experiment. Blue flowers became risky and yellow flowers became non-variable.

Bees overwhelmingly preferred the "less risky" reward flower, even though on average they have exactly the same reward (e.g., 2 ul/flower). Also, they switched from blue to yellow when the reward structure changed from blue with a non-variable reward and yellow with a risky reward to blue as a risky reward and yellow with a non-variable reward. One can even provide the bees with more profitable but risky flowers and they still choose the less variable flower!

71% choice for the less risky flowers

versus 50:50 predicted

Why are Bumble Bees Risk Aversive in Foraging?

Cognition and Bumble Bee Foraging

There are a number of plausible hypotheses, however, Les Real has explored the possibility that their choice may be imposed by cognitive constraints of memory on foraging. Cognition is defined in terms of three items (Real 1993):

  1. perception -- a unit of information from the environment is collected and stored in memory,
  2. data manipulation -- several units of information that are stored in memory are analyzed according to computational rules built into the nervous system,
  3. forming a representation of the environment -- a complete "picture" is formed from the processing of all the information and the organism bases its decision on the complete picture or representation of the environment.

Lets think of a simple model for memory and how it might influence foraging. Imagine that a Bumble Bee has a specified list of items in its memory that describe the profitability of items during bouts of foraging. It has also been termed a memory window.

E1/T1 (last item encountered)

E2/T2 (second last item encountered)

E3/T3 (etc)....

If a bumble bee can only remember the last item upon which it foraged (e.g., E1/T1) then a very short memory might easily explain their behavior.

Odds are 2:1 that a bumble bee will encounter 0 when feeding on the variable reward flower. Thus, it would tend to avoid such flowers if the rule dictates that the decision to visit the next flower is based upon last flower encountered. Thus, a Bumble Bee feeding on the non-varying flower would perceive that it was feeding on the flower with the highest reward. It would then tend to seek out flowers with the same color.

Is a list length a constraint or an adaptation?

Real argues that such list lengths might be adaptive and not just a constraint. If the food items are distributed randomly in the environment, then list lengths are of no use to a forager. Feeding at one flower provides no information about the next flower encountered. However, if the flowers are clumped in the environment, then feeding at a flower will provide information about nearby flowers and the foraging Bumble Bee should remember the reward and use that information in the decision to either continue feeding in the clump of flowers or leave the clump in search of better. Real is collecting data on this aspect of the model as we speak.


Additional References:

Science 1991 vol 253 980-986

Am Nat 140 suppl nov 92 s108-s145

Real and Caracao Ann Rev Ecol Syst vol 17:371-390

Index


Foraging in Juncos Under Food Limitation

Caracao has studied the risk aversive foraging in juncos. Juncos show the same aversion to highly variable rewards that are seen in bees. However, if you food deprive the juncos and make them energy limited, they switch from risk aversive foraging, to a mode that tends to select variable, but more profitable rewards. In the example of Bumble Bee Foraging it is difficult to reconcile risk aversion as being strictly adaptive and the arguments regarding their choices relate to the bumble bees as built to avoid risk in the environment (e.g., it is a product of their memory window).

Caracao demonstrated that well fed juncos are similarly risk aversive. However if you make them energy limited to the point where they face death, they then will be pushed to adopt the risk seeking strategy that has a higher pay-off.

To test this principle Caracao seek up two pans: the first with a non-variable modest reward and the second pan with a variable but higher pay-off reward.

He tested the birds under conditions of non-energy limitation and conditions of energy deprivation. The birds that were non-energy limited chose the lower payoff pan over the more risky, but higher payoff pan. When food limitation became a factor they then opted for the higher payoff but risky pan.


The Big Picture for Risk Aversive Behavior

Risk Aversive Behavior when not food limited is a case in which the behaviors of the animals are not following strict optimization rules. While researchers believe that there are still some things we do not understand about this behavior some hypotheses relate to the possibility that memory and cognitive constraints might limit the adaptive decision making in some way. Such memory constraints exist at the level of the proximate constraints that govern the processing of information and we will explore these topics in greater detail in subsequent chapters.

Index


Foraging and Biotic Interactions

All of the examples described above have an organism making decisions in the absence of any real biological interactions. In the following section we will briefly explore other factors that might influence the decision making of organisms.

Index


Group Foraging

Why forage in groups?

If group foraging is adaptive then an organisms foraging in a group must experience a higher payoff than if it were foraging alone. Data collected on lions (Caracao and Wolf) illustrate the costs and benefits of group foraging.

Capture efficiency rises as a function of the number of members in a group of lions, however, the curve levels off at large group sizes because additional lions do not improve the odds of taking down a Thompson gazelle.

Food availability per lion from the kill is a declining function of group size.

Food intake per lion shows an optimal group size to be two lions, not the 4-7 members observed in a group. Food intake takes into account the success in foraging (capture efficiency) and the food availability.

Why do lions forage in larger than optimal groups?

This question is not yet resolved, but it is thought that it might arise from kin selection and reasons other than foraging. Sisters may band together in larger than expected groups because they can better able prevent males lions from practicing infanticide (see Alcock's discussion of lion infanticide in Chapter 1).

There may also be information transfer among members of the group even if they are not aiding one another in taking down prey. For example, Eric Greene (1987) demonstrated that nesting osprey in a colony pay attention to which birds came back with successful prey items, and if they followed such birds on successive bouts, they too were more likely to be successful themselves.

Index


Predation Risk

For other organisms on the predated end of the spectrum, group foraging might also alleviate the risk of predation. If an animal is solitary then the behavior that it demonstrates with regard to foraging may not be optimal because it must also be vigilant to predators. Many studies have demonstrated that the animals forage in different ways with predators present than with predators absent.

However, if animals are foraging in a group, then not every animal must be vigilant. There are designated watchers that alert the group when predators are near. Even if everyone still maintains some level of vigilance (e.g., they are not altruists) then more eyes watching lowers the overall risk of predation than if only two eyes are watching.

Index


Back to the Syllabus